Philosophical problems for an environmental ethic

advertisement
Philosophical problems for an
environmental ethic
We’ve seen that using economic approaches to placing a value on biological diversity
poses great challenges, and we’ve seen that an important part of using those approaches
must be incorporating non-use values into the economic framework. We’ve just finished a
very brief review of philosophical approaches to ethics, and I’ve already suggested that under
both consequentialist and some non-consequentialist views biodiversity seems to have only
instrumental value. Now it’s vital to remember that instrumental value is not the same
thing as use value.
• Use values are those derived either from using a resource, e.g., the commercial value
of lumber extracted from a forest, or from the costs we incur from failing to protect a
resource, e.g., the cost of levees and dams used to control river flooding when floodplain
wetlands are converted to residential or industrial use.
• Non-use values include those associated with pleasure or appreciation, i.e., aesthetic
values, and those associated with obligation or duty, i.e., ethical values.
It is therefore not problematic for an adherent of any ethical system to incorporate non-use
values of biodiversity into decisions about what is right or just, so long as the non-use values
concerned are aesthetic values. An interesting question is, however, is there some sense in
which we have a duty, an ethical or moral obligation, to conserve biodiversity (or protect the
biological integrity of a system or ensure the ecological sustainability of our use of a system
and its resources)?1
The problem of holism
As Sober [3] points out one particularly important distinction to keep in mind: The things
on which an environmental ethich would place value are whole species, communities, or
1
I’m going to use the phrase “conserve biodiversity” throughout the rest of these notes. I don’t mean to
imply that conserving biodiversity is the only thing we might have an ethical obligation to do towards the
environment. I just don’t want to repeat myself constantly.
c 2001 Kent E. Holsinger
ecosystems, not the individual organisms of which they are composed.
• Consider the question of whether to control the size of deer populations in reserves
maintained by The Nature Conservancy. Many would agree that such management is
needed to conserve the species and communities within those reserves.
• Philosophers like Peter Singer [2] argue that we have an ethical obligation to prevent the
suffering of individual animals. On this view, management of deer populations would
be unethical if it involves any harm to individual deer, e.g., by allowing hunters to kill
some deer, even if this harm to individual deer was beneficial to other conservation
values associated with the preserve.
• Jane Goodall has been criticized by some conservationists for devoting too much attention to the welfare of individual chimpanzees and to little attention to the “broader”
issues of ensuring that chimpanzees have the habitat they need to survive in the wild.
Suggesting that we have a duty to a whole species, as opposed to its individual members, is
analogous to the way we often suggest that we have a duty to a group, e.g., our department,
the University, the profession, our country, that goes beyond our obligation to the individual
members of that group. Moreover, we often recognize a conflict between our duty to individuals and our duty to a group, e.g., the conflict between individual liberties and national
security.
The problem of “natural”
“Every ethical theory must provide principles that describe which objects matter for their
own sakes and which do not” [3, p. 188]. So how do we determine that species, to take one
example, “matter for their own sake?” In particular, how do we determine that causing a
species to go extinct is “bad” and that preventing its extinction is “good,” especially when
we remember that the eventual fate of every species is extinction?2 The response I gave in
one of the first lectures in this class was that the current rate of extinction is much higher
than it has been at any time in the recent geological past. But why is a high extinction rate
bad?
One response might be that it isn’t a “natural” rate of extinction. It’s a “human-caused”
rate of extinction. That seems plausible, but it raises another issue:
2
The reason everything isn’t extinct is that some species give rise to one or more new species before they
go extinct.
2
If we are part of nature, then everything we do is part of nature, and is natural in
the primary sense. When we domesticate organisms and bring them into a state
of dependence on us, this is simply an example of one species exerting a selection
pressure on another. If one calls this “unnatural,” one might just as well say the
same of parasitism or symbiosis (compare human domestication of animals and
plants and “slave-making” in the social insects).[3, p. 180]
Similarly, if humans are causing a higher rate of extinction and we are part of nature, how
can we say that human-caused extinctions are unnatural?
As Callicott et al. point out [1] whether we regard humans as part of the system or not
goes well beyond simply noting that we are evolutionarily related to all other living things
on this planet. The answer depends on whether we take a more compositionalist view of
ecosystems or a more functionalist view.
• Compositionalists view the biotic world as consisting of organisms that are aggregated
into populations, communities, and ecosystems.
• Functionalists view the biotic world as consisting of physical and chemical processes
associated with energy flow and nutrient cycling.
• Compositionalists tend to think of human beings as separate from nature “because
culture uniquely enables Homo sapiens to adapt . . . orders of magnitude than can
other species . . . ” [1, p. 24].
• Functionalists tend to think of human beings as part of nature because “human dissipative structures do not stand out so sharply from others of comparable size and
distribution” [1, p. 24].
Callicott et al. suggest that biological diversity, biological integrity, and ecological restoration are values typically associated with a compositionalist approach, while ecosystem health,
ecological services, adaptive management, ecosystem management, sustainable development,
ecological sustainability, and ecological rehabilitation are values typically associated with a
functionalist approach. They argue that a synthetic approach combining insights of both is
needed.
There’s one final question that we’ve skirted throughout these discussions that I want
to mention, not answer, before closing the book on this semester: Who gets to make the
decisions about conservation policy?
• If I am committed to democracy and individual rights, I must also be committed to
the right of others to choose differently from me, even if they make what I think is the
wrong choice.
3
• If I am also committed to conserving biological diversity, I must either be convinced
that I can persuade others of the rightness of my views so that the policies I favor will
be democratically adopted, be willing to accept a democratic decision allowing policies
that will harm conservation values I hold dear, or be willing to believe that my opinion
matters more than the opinion of those who don’t value biodiversity as highly as I do
and make policies for them that’s in their own best interest.
References
[1] J. B. Callicott, L. B. Crowder, and K. Mumford. Current normative concepts in conservation. Conservation Biology, 13:22–35, 1999.
[2] P. Singer. Animal Liberation. Random House, New York, NY, 1975.
[3] E. Sober. Philosophical problems for environmentalism. In B. G. Norton, editor, The
Preservation of Species: The Value of Biological Diversity, pages 173–194. Princeton
University Press, Princeton, NJ, 1986.
4
Download